Nicomachean Ethics
By Aristotle
Commentary: Quite a few comments have been posted about
Nicomachean Ethics.
Download: A
text-only version is available for download.
Nicomachean Ethics
By Aristotle
Written 350 B.C.E
Translated by W. D. Ross
1
After these matters we ought perhaps next to discuss pleasure.
For it is thought to be most intimately connected with our human nature,
which is the reason why in educating the young we steer them by the rudders
of pleasure and pain; it is thought, too, that to enjoy the things we ought
and to hate the things we ought has the greatest bearing on virtue of character.
For these things extend right through life, with a weight and power of
their own in respect both to virtue and to the happy life, since men choose
what is pleasant and avoid what is painful; and such things, it will be
thought, we should least of all omit to discuss, especially since they
admit of much dispute. For some say pleasure is the good, while others,
on the contrary, say it is thoroughly bad-some no doubt being persuaded
that the facts are so, and others thinking it has a better effect on our
life to exhibit pleasure as a bad thing even if it is not; for most people
(they think) incline towards it and are the slaves of their pleasures,
for which reason they ought to lead them in the opposite direction, since
thus they will reach the middle state. But surely this is not correct.
For arguments about matters concerned with feelings and actions are less
reliable than facts: and so when they clash with the facts of perception
they are despised, and discredit the truth as well; if a man who runs down
pleasure is once seen to be alming at it, his inclining towards it is thought
to imply that it is all worthy of being aimed at; for most people are not
good at drawing distinctions. True arguments seem, then, most useful, not
only with a view to knowledge, but with a view to life also; for since
they harmonize with the facts they are believed, and so they stimulate
those who understand them to live according to them.-Enough of such questions;
let us proceed to review the opinions that have been expressed about
pleasure.
2
Eudoxus thought pleasure was the good because he saw all things,
both rational and irrational, aiming at it, and because in all things that
which is the object of choice is what is excellent, and that which is most
the object of choice the greatest good; thus the fact that all things moved
towards the same object indicated that this was for all things the chief
good (for each thing, he argued, finds its own good, as it finds its own
nourishment); and that which is good for all things and at which all aim
was the good. His arguments were credited more because of the excellence
of his character than for their own sake; he was thought to be remarkably
self-controlled, and therefore it was thought that he was not saying what
he did say as a friend of pleasure, but that the facts really were so.
He believed that the same conclusion followed no less plainly from a study
of the contrary of pleasure; pain was in itself an object of aversion to
all things, and therefore its contrary must be similarly an object of choice.
And again that is most an object of choice which we choose not because
or for the sake of something else, and pleasure is admittedly of this nature;
for no one asks to what end he is pleased, thus implying that pleasure
is in itself an object of choice. Further, he argued that pleasure when
added to any good, e.g. to just or temperate action, makes it more worthy
of choice, and that it is only by itself that the good can be
increased.
This argument seems to show it to be one of the goods, and no more
a good than any other; for every good is more worthy of choice along with
another good than taken alone. And so it is by an argument of this kind
that Plato proves the good not to be pleasure; he argues that the pleasant
life is more desirable with wisdom than without, and that if the mixture
is better, pleasure is not the good; for the good cannot become more desirable
by the addition of anything to it. Now it is clear that nothing else, any
more than pleasure, can be the good if it is made more desirable by the
addition of any of the things that are good in themselves. What, then,
is there that satisfies this criterion, which at the same time we can participate
in? It is something of this sort that we are looking for. Those who object
that that at which all things aim is not necessarily good are, we may surmise,
talking nonsense. For we say that that which every one thinks really is
so; and the man who attacks this belief will hardly have anything more
credible to maintain instead. If it is senseless creatures that desire
the things in question, there might be something in what they say; but
if intelligent creatures do so as well, what sense can there be in this
view? But perhaps even in inferior creatures there is some natural good
stronger than themselves which aims at their proper
good.
Nor does the argument about the contrary of pleasure seem to be
correct. They say that if pain is an evil it does not follow that pleasure
is a good; for evil is opposed to evil and at the same time both are opposed
to the neutral state-which is correct enough but does not apply to the
things in question. For if both pleasure and pain belonged to the class
of evils they ought both to be objects of aversion, while if they belonged
to the class of neutrals neither should be an object of aversion or they
should both be equally so; but in fact people evidently avoid the one as
evil and choose the other as good; that then must be the nature of the
opposition between them.
3
Nor again, if pleasure is not a quality, does it follow that it
is not a good; for the activities of virtue are not qualities either, nor
is happiness. They say, however, that the good is determinate, while pleasure
is indeterminate, because it admits of degrees. Now if it is from the feeling
of pleasure that they judge thus, the same will be true of justice and
the other virtues, in respect of which we plainly say that people of a
certain character are so more or less, and act more or less in accordance
with these virtues; for people may be more just or brave, and it is possible
also to act justly or temperately more or less. But if their judgement
is based on the various pleasures, surely they are not stating the real
cause, if in fact some pleasures are unmixed and others mixed. Again, just
as health admits of degrees without being indeterminate, why should not
pleasure? The same proportion is not found in all things, nor a single
proportion always in the same thing, but it may be relaxed and yet persist
up to a point, and it may differ in degree. The case of pleasure also may
therefore be of this kind.
Again, they assume that the good is perfect while movements and
comings into being are imperfect, and try to exhibit pleasure as being
a movement and a coming into being. But they do not seem to be right even
in saying that it is a movement. For speed and slowness are thought to
be proper to every movement, and if a movement, e.g. that of the heavens,
has not speed or slowness in itself, it has it in relation to something
else; but of pleasure neither of these things is true. For while we may
become pleased quickly as we may become angry quickly, we cannot be pleased
quickly, not even in relation to some one else, while we can walk, or grow,
or the like, quickly. While, then, we can change quickly or slowly into
a state of pleasure, we cannot quickly exhibit the activity of pleasure,
i.e. be pleased. Again, how can it be a coming into being? It is not thought
that any chance thing can come out of any chance thing, but that a thing
is dissolved into that out of which it comes into being; and pain would
be the destruction of that of which pleasure is the coming into
being.
They say, too, that pain is the lack of that which is according
to nature, and pleasure is replenishment. But these experiences are bodily.
If then pleasure is replenishment with that which is according to nature,
that which feels pleasure will be that in which the replenishment takes
place, i.e. the body; but that is not thought to be the case; therefore
the replenishment is not pleasure, though one would be pleased when replenishment
was taking place, just as one would be pained if one was being operated
on. This opinion seems to be based on the pains and pleasures connected
with nutrition; on the fact that when people have been short of food and
have felt pain beforehand they are pleased by the replenishment. But this
does not happen with all pleasures; for the pleasures of learning and,
among the sensuous pleasures, those of smell, and also many sounds and
sights, and memories and hopes, do not presuppose pain. Of what then will
these be the coming into being? There has not been lack of anything of
which they could be the supplying anew.
In reply to those who bring forward the disgraceful pleasures one
may say that these are not pleasant; if things are pleasant to people of
vicious constitution, we must not suppose that they are also pleasant to
others than these, just as we do not reason so about the things that are
wholesome or sweet or bitter to sick people, or ascribe whiteness to the
things that seem white to those suffering from a disease of the eye. Or
one might answer thus-that the pleasures are desirable, but not from these
sources, as wealth is desirable, but not as the reward of betrayal, and
health, but not at the cost of eating anything and everything. Or perhaps
pleasures differ in kind; for those derived from noble sources are different
from those derived from base sources, and one cannot the pleasure of the
just man without being just, nor that of the musical man without being
musical, and so on.
The fact, too, that a friend is different from a flatterer seems
to make it plain that pleasure is not a good or that pleasures are different
in kind; for the one is thought to consort with us with a view to the good,
the other with a view to our pleasure, and the one is reproached for his
conduct while the other is praised on the ground that he consorts with
us for different ends. And no one would choose to live with the intellect
of a child throughout his life, however much he were to be pleased at the
things that children are pleased at, nor to get enjoyment by doing some
most disgraceful deed, though he were never to feel any pain in consequence.
And there are many things we should be keen about even if they brought
no pleasure, e.g. seeing, remembering, knowing, possessing the virtues.
If pleasures necessarily do accompany these, that makes no odds; we should
choose these even if no pleasure resulted. It seems to be clear, then,
that neither is pleasure the good nor is all pleasure desirable, and that
some pleasures are desirable in themselves, differing in kind or in their
sources from the others. So much for the things that are said about pleasure
and pain.
4
What pleasure is, or what kind of thing it is, will become plainer
if we take up the question aga from the beginning. Seeing seems to be at
any moment complete, for it does not lack anything which coming into being
later will complete its form; and pleasure also seems to be of this nature.
For it is a whole, and at no time can one find a pleasure whose form will
be completed if the pleasure lasts longer. For this reason, too, it is
not a movement. For every movement (e.g. that of building) takes time and
is for the sake of an end, and is complete when it has made what it aims
at. It is complete, therefore, only in the whole time or at that final
moment. In their parts and during the time they occupy, all movements are
incomplete, and are different in kind from the whole movement and from
each other. For the fitting together of the stones is different from the
fluting of the column, and these are both different from the making of
the temple; and the making of the temple is complete (for it lacks nothing
with a view to the end proposed), but the making of the base or of the
triglyph is incomplete; for each is the making of only a part. They differ
in kind, then, and it is not possible to find at any and every time a movement
complete in form, but if at all, only in the whole time. So, too, in the
case of walking and all other movements. For if locomotion is a movement
from to there, it, too, has differences in kind-flying, walking, leaping,
and so on. And not only so, but in walking itself there are such differences;
for the whence and whither are not the same in the whole racecourse and
in a part of it, nor in one part and in another, nor is it the same thing
to traverse this line and that; for one traverses not only a line but one
which is in a place, and this one is in a different place from that. We
have discussed movement with precision in another work, but it seems that
it is not complete at any and every time, but that the many movements are
incomplete and different in kind, since the whence and whither give them
their form. But of pleasure the form is complete at any and every time.
Plainly, then, pleasure and movement must be different from each other,
and pleasure must be one of the things that are whole and complete. This
would seem to be the case, too, from the fact that it is not possible to
move otherwise than in time, but it is possible to be pleased; for that
which takes place in a moment is a whole.
From these considerations it is clear, too, that these thinkers
are not right in saying there is a movement or a coming into being of pleasure.
For these cannot be ascribed to all things, but only to those that are
divisible and not wholes; there is no coming into being of seeing nor of
a point nor of a unit, nor is any of these a movement or coming into being;
therefore there is no movement or coming into being of pleasure either;
for it is a whole.
Since every sense is active in relation to its object, and a sense
which is in good condition acts perfectly in relation to the most beautiful
of its objects (for perfect activity seems to be ideally of this nature;
whether we say that it is active, or the organ in which it resides, may
be assumed to be immaterial), it follows that in the case of each sense
the best activity is that of the best-conditioned organ in relation to
the finest of its objects. And this activity will be the most complete
and pleasant. For, while there is pleasure in respect of any sense, and
in respect of thought and contemplation no less, the most complete is pleasantest,
and that of a well-conditioned organ in relation to the worthiest of its
objects is the most complete; and the pleasure completes the activity.
But the pleasure does not complete it in the same way as the combination
of object and sense, both good, just as health and the doctor are not in
the same way the cause of a man's being healthy. (That pleasure is produced
in respect to each sense is plain; for we speak of sights and sounds as
pleasant. It is also plain that it arises most of all when both the sense
is at its best and it is active in reference to an object which corresponds;
when both object and perceiver are of the best there will always be pleasure,
since the requisite agent and patient are both present.) Pleasure completes
the activity not as the corresponding permanent state does, by its immanence,
but as an end which supervenes as the bloom of youth does on those in the
flower of their age. So long, then, as both the intelligible or sensible
object and the discriminating or contemplative faculty are as they should
be, the pleasure will be involved in the activity; for when both the passive
and the active factor are unchanged and are related to each other in the
same way, the same result naturally follows.
How, then, is it that no one is continuously pleased? Is it that
we grow weary? Certainly all human beings are incapable of continuous activity.
Therefore pleasure also is not continuous; for it accompanies activity.
Some things delight us when they are new, but later do so less, for the
same reason; for at first the mind is in a state of stimulation and intensely
active about them, as people are with respect to their vision when they
look hard at a thing, but afterwards our activity is not of this kind,
but has grown relaxed; for which reason the pleasure also is
dulled.
One might think that all men desire pleasure because they all aim
at life; life is an activity, and each man is active about those things
and with those faculties that he loves most; e.g. the musician is active
with his hearing in reference to tunes, the student with his mind in reference
to theoretical questions, and so on in each case; now pleasure completes
the activities, and therefore life, which they desire. It is with good
reason, then, that they aim at pleasure too, since for every one it completes
life, which is desirable. But whether we choose life for the sake of pleasure
or pleasure for the sake of life is a question we may dismiss for the present.
For they seem to be bound up together and not to admit of separation, since
without activity pleasure does not arise, and every activity is completed
by the attendant pleasure.
5
For this reason pleasures seem, too, to differ in kind. For things
different in kind are, we think, completed by different things (we see
this to be true both of natural objects and of things produced by art,
e.g. animals, trees, a painting, a sculpture, a house, an implement); and,
similarly, we think that activities differing in kind are completed by
things differing in kind. Now the activities of thought differ from those
of the senses, and both differ among themselves, in kind; so, therefore,
do the pleasures that complete them.
This may be seen, too, from the fact that each of the pleasures
is bound up with the activity it completes. For an activity is intensified
by its proper pleasure, since each class of things is better judged of
and brought to precision by those who engage in the activity with pleasure;
e.g. it is those who enjoy geometrical thinking that become geometers and
grasp the various propositions better, and, similarly, those who are fond
of music or of building, and so on, make progress in their proper function
by enjoying it; so the pleasures intensify the activities, and what intensifies
a thing is proper to it, but things different in kind have properties different
in kind.
This will be even more apparent from the fact that activities are
hindered by pleasures arising from other sources. For people who are fond
of playing the flute are incapable of attending to arguments if they overhear
some one playing the flute, since they enjoy flute-playing more than the
activity in hand; so the pleasure connected with fluteplaying destroys
the activity concerned with argument. This happens, similarly, in all other
cases, when one is active about two things at once; the more pleasant activity
drives out the other, and if it is much more pleasant does so all the more,
so that one even ceases from the other. This is why when we enjoy anything
very much we do not throw ourselves into anything else, and do one thing
only when we are not much pleased by another; e.g. in the theatre the people
who eat sweets do so most when the actors are poor. Now since activities
are made precise and more enduring and better by their proper pleasure,
and injured by alien pleasures, evidently the two kinds of pleasure are
far apart. For alien pleasures do pretty much what proper pains do, since
activities are destroyed by their proper pains; e.g. if a man finds writing
or doing sums unpleasant and painful, he does not write, or does not do
sums, because the activity is painful. So an activity suffers contrary
effects from its proper pleasures and pains, i.e. from those that supervene
on it in virtue of its own nature. And alien pleasures have been stated
to do much the same as pain; they destroy the activity, only not to the
same degree.
Now since activities differ in respect of goodness and badness,
and some are worthy to be chosen, others to be avoided, and others neutral,
so, too, are the pleasures; for to each activity there is a proper pleasure.
The pleasure proper to a worthy activity is good and that proper to an
unworthy activity bad; just as the appetites for noble objects are laudable,
those for base objects culpable. But the pleasures involved in activities
are more proper to them than the desires; for the latter are separated
both in time and in nature, while the former are close to the activities,
and so hard to distinguish from them that it admits of dispute whether
the activity is not the same as the pleasure. (Still, pleasure does not
seem to be thought or perception-that would be strange; but because they
are not found apart they appear to some people the same.) As activities
are different, then, so are the corresponding pleasures. Now sight is superior
to touch in purity, and hearing and smell to taste; the pleasures, therefore,
are similarly superior, and those of thought superior to these, and within
each of the two kinds some are superior to others.
Each animal is thought to have a proper pleasure, as it has a proper
function; viz. that which corresponds to its activity. If we survey them
species by species, too, this will be evident; horse, dog, and man have
different pleasures, as Heraclitus says 'asses would prefer sweepings to
gold'; for food is pleasanter than gold to asses. So the pleasures of creatures
different in kind differ in kind, and it is plausible to suppose that those
of a single species do not differ. But they vary to no small extent, in
the case of men at least; the same things delight some people and pain
others, and are painful and odious to some, and pleasant to and liked by
others. This happens, too, in the case of sweet things; the same things
do not seem sweet to a man in a fever and a healthy man-nor hot to a weak
man and one in good condition. The same happens in other cases. But in
all such matters that which appears to the good man is thought to be really
so. If this is correct, as it seems to be, and virtue and the good man
as such are the measure of each thing, those also will be pleasures which
appear so to him, and those things pleasant which he enjoys. If the things
he finds tiresome seem pleasant to some one, that is nothing surprising;
for men may be ruined and spoilt in many ways; but the things are not pleasant,
but only pleasant to these people and to people in this condition. Those
which are admittedly disgraceful plainly should not be said to be pleasures,
except to a perverted taste; but of those that are thought to be good what
kind of pleasure or what pleasure should be said to be that proper to man?
Is it not plain from the corresponding activities? The pleasures follow
these. Whether, then, the perfect and supremely happy man has one or more
activities, the pleasures that perfect these will be said in the strict
sense to be pleasures proper to man, and the rest will be so in a secondary
and fractional way, as are the activities.
6
Now that we have spoken of the virtues, the forms of friendship,
and the varieties of pleasure, what remains is to discuss in outline the
nature of happiness, since this is what we state the end of human nature
to be. Our discussion will be the more concise if we first sum up what
we have said already. We said, then, that it is not a disposition; for
if it were it might belong to some one who was asleep throughout his life,
living the life of a plant, or, again, to some one who was suffering the
greatest misfortunes. If these implications are unacceptable, and we must
rather class happiness as an activity, as we have said before, and if some
activities are necessary, and desirable for the sake of something else,
while others are so in themselves, evidently happiness must be placed among
those desirable in themselves, not among those desirable for the sake of
something else; for happiness does not lack anything, but is self-sufficient.
Now those activities are desirable in themselves from which nothing is
sought beyond the activity. And of this nature virtuous actions are thought
to be; for to do noble and good deeds is a thing desirable for its own
sake.
Pleasant amusements also are thought to be of this nature; we choose
them not for the sake of other things; for we are injured rather than benefited
by them, since we are led to neglect our bodies and our property. But most
of the people who are deemed happy take refuge in such pastimes, which
is the reason why those who are ready-witted at them are highly esteemed
at the courts of tyrants; they make themselves pleasant companions in the
tyrants' favourite pursuits, and that is the sort of man they want. Now
these things are thought to be of the nature of happiness because people
in despotic positions spend their leisure in them, but perhaps such people
prove nothing; for virtue and reason, from which good activities flow,
do not depend on despotic position; nor, if these people, who have never
tasted pure and generous pleasure, take refuge in the bodily pleasures,
should these for that reason be thought more desirable; for boys, too,
think the things that are valued among themselves are the best. It is to
be expected, then, that, as different things seem valuable to boys and
to men, so they should to bad men and to good. Now, as we have often maintained,
those things are both valuable and pleasant which are such to the good
man; and to each man the activity in accordance with his own disposition
is most desirable, and, therefore, to the good man that which is in accordance
with virtue. Happiness, therefore, does not lie in amusement; it would,
indeed, be strange if the end were amusement, and one were to take trouble
and suffer hardship all one's life in order to amuse oneself. For, in a
word, everything that we choose we choose for the sake of something else-except
happiness, which is an end. Now to exert oneself and work for the sake
of amusement seems silly and utterly childish. But to amuse oneself in
order that one may exert oneself, as Anacharsis puts it, seems right; for
amusement is a sort of relaxation, and we need relaxation because we cannot
work continuously. Relaxation, then, is not an end; for it is taken for
the sake of activity.
The happy life is thought to be virtuous; now a virtuous life requires
exertion, and does not consist in amusement. And we say that serious things
are better than laughable things and those connected with amusement, and
that the activity of the better of any two things-whether it be two elements
of our being or two men-is the more serious; but the activity of the better
is ipso facto superior and more of the nature of happiness. And any chance
person-even a slave-can enjoy the bodily pleasures no less than the best
man; but no one assigns to a slave a share in happiness-unless he assigns
to him also a share in human life. For happiness does not lie in such occupations,
but, as we have said before, in virtuous activities.
7
If happiness is activity in accordance with virtue, it is reasonable
that it should be in accordance with the highest virtue; and this will
be that of the best thing in us. Whether it be reason or something else
that is this element which is thought to be our natural ruler and guide
and to take thought of things noble and divine, whether it be itself also
divine or only the most divine element in us, the activity of this in accordance
with its proper virtue will be perfect happiness. That this activity is
contemplative we have already said.
Now this would seem to be in agreement both with what we said before
and with the truth. For, firstly, this activity is the best (since not
only is reason the best thing in us, but the objects of reason are the
best of knowable objects); and secondly, it is the most continuous, since
we can contemplate truth more continuously than we can do anything. And
we think happiness has pleasure mingled with it, but the activity of philosophic
wisdom is admittedly the pleasantest of virtuous activities; at all events
the pursuit of it is thought to offer pleasures marvellous for their purity
and their enduringness, and it is to be expected that those who know will
pass their time more pleasantly than those who inquire. And the self-sufficiency
that is spoken of must belong most to the contemplative activity. For while
a philosopher, as well as a just man or one possessing any other virtue,
needs the necessaries of life, when they are sufficiently equipped with
things of that sort the just man needs people towards whom and with whom
he shall act justly, and the temperate man, the brave man, and each of
the others is in the same case, but the philosopher, even when by himself,
can contemplate truth, and the better the wiser he is; he can perhaps do
so better if he has fellow-workers, but still he is the most self-sufficient.
And this activity alone would seem to be loved for its own sake; for nothing
arises from it apart from the contemplating, while from practical activities
we gain more or less apart from the action. And happiness is thought to
depend on leisure; for we are busy that we may have leisure, and make war
that we may live in peace. Now the activity of the practical virtues is
exhibited in political or military affairs, but the actions concerned with
these seem to be unleisurely. Warlike actions are completely so (for no
one chooses to be at war, or provokes war, for the sake of being at war;
any one would seem absolutely murderous if he were to make enemies of his
friends in order to bring about battle and slaughter); but the action of
the statesman is also unleisurely, and-apart from the political action
itself-aims at despotic power and honours, or at all events happiness,
for him and his fellow citizens-a happiness different from political action,
and evidently sought as being different. So if among virtuous actions political
and military actions are distinguished by nobility and greatness, and these
are unleisurely and aim at an end and are not desirable for their own sake,
but the activity of reason, which is contemplative, seems both to be superior
in serious worth and to aim at no end beyond itself, and to have its pleasure
proper to itself (and this augments the activity), and the self-sufficiency,
leisureliness, unweariedness (so far as this is possible for man), and
all the other attributes ascribed to the supremely happy man are evidently
those connected with this activity, it follows that this will be the complete
happiness of man, if it be allowed a complete term of life (for none of
the attributes of happiness is incomplete).
But such a life would be too high for man; for it is not in so
far as he is man that he will live so, but in so far as something divine
is present in him; and by so much as this is superior to our composite
nature is its activity superior to that which is the exercise of the other
kind of virtue. If reason is divine, then, in comparison with man, the
life according to it is divine in comparison with human life. But we must
not follow those who advise us, being men, to think of human things, and,
being mortal, of mortal things, but must, so far as we can, make ourselves
immortal, and strain every nerve to live in accordance with the best thing
in us; for even if it be small in bulk, much more does it in power and
worth surpass everything. This would seem, too, to be each man himself,
since it is the authoritative and better part of him. It would be strange,
then, if he were to choose not the life of his self but that of something
else. And what we said before' will apply now; that which is proper to
each thing is by nature best and most pleasant for each thing; for man,
therefore, the life according to reason is best and pleasantest, since
reason more than anything else is man. This life therefore is also the
happiest.
8
But in a secondary degree the life in accordance with the other
kind of virtue is happy; for the activities in accordance with this befit
our human estate. Just and brave acts, and other virtuous acts, we do in
relation to each other, observing our respective duties with regard to
contracts and services and all manner of actions and with regard to passions;
and all of these seem to be typically human. Some of them seem even to
arise from the body, and virtue of character to be in many ways bound up
with the passions. Practical wisdom, too, is linked to virtue of character,
and this to practical wisdom, since the principles of practical wisdom
are in accordance with the moral virtues and rightness in morals is in
accordance with practical wisdom. Being connected with the passions also,
the moral virtues must belong to our composite nature; and the virtues
of our composite nature are human; so, therefore, are the life and the
happiness which correspond to these. The excellence of the reason is a
thing apart; we must be content to say this much about it, for to describe
it precisely is a task greater than our purpose requires. It would seem,
however, also to need external equipment but little, or less than moral
virtue does. Grant that both need the necessaries, and do so equally, even
if the statesman's work is the more concerned with the body and things
of that sort; for there will be little difference there; but in what they
need for the exercise of their activities there will be much difference.
The liberal man will need money for the doing of his liberal deeds, and
the just man too will need it for the returning of services (for wishes
are hard to discern, and even people who are not just pretend to wish to
act justly); and the brave man will need power if he is to accomplish any
of the acts that correspond to his virtue, and the temperate man will need
opportunity; for how else is either he or any of the others to be recognized?
It is debated, too, whether the will or the deed is more essential to virtue,
which is assumed to involve both; it is surely clear that its perfection
involves both; but for deeds many things are needed, and more, the greater
and nobler the deeds are. But the man who is contemplating the truth needs
no such thing, at least with a view to the exercise of his activity; indeed
they are, one may say, even hindrances, at all events to his contemplation;
but in so far as he is a man and lives with a number of people, he chooses
to do virtuous acts; he will therefore need such aids to living a human
life.
But that perfect happiness is a contemplative activity will appear
from the following consideration as well. We assume the gods to be above
all other beings blessed and happy; but what sort of actions must we assign
to them? Acts of justice? Will not the gods seem absurd if they make contracts
and return deposits, and so on? Acts of a brave man, then, confronting
dangers and running risks because it is noble to do so? Or liberal acts?
To whom will they give? It will be strange if they are really to have money
or anything of the kind. And what would their temperate acts be? Is not
such praise tasteless, since they have no bad appetites? If we were to
run through them all, the circumstances of action would be found trivial
and unworthy of gods. Still, every one supposes that they live and therefore
that they are active; we cannot suppose them to sleep like Endymion. Now
if you take away from a living being action, and still more production,
what is left but contemplation? Therefore the activity of God, which surpasses
all others in blessedness, must be contemplative; and of human activities,
therefore, that which is most akin to this must be most of the nature of
happiness.
This is indicated, too, by the fact that the other animals have
no share in happiness, being completely deprived of such activity. For
while the whole life of the gods is blessed, and that of men too in so
far as some likeness of such activity belongs to them, none of the other
animals is happy, since they in no way share in contemplation. Happiness
extends, then, just so far as contemplation does, and those to whom contemplation
more fully belongs are more truly happy, not as a mere concomitant but
in virtue of the contemplation; for this is in itself precious. Happiness,
therefore, must be some form of contemplation.
But, being a man, one will also need external prosperity; for our
nature is not self-sufficient for the purpose of contemplation, but our
body also must be healthy and must have food and other attention. Still,
we must not think that the man who is to be happy will need many things
or great things, merely because he cannot be supremely happy without external
goods; for self-sufficiency and action do not involve excess, and we can
do noble acts without ruling earth and sea; for even with moderate advantages
one can act virtuously (this is manifest enough; for private persons are
thought to do worthy acts no less than despots-indeed even more); and it
is enough that we should have so much as that; for the life of the man
who is active in accordance with virtue will be happy. Solon, too, was
perhaps sketching well the happy man when he described him as moderately
furnished with externals but as having done (as Solon thought) the noblest
acts, and lived temperately; for one can with but moderate possessions
do what one ought. Anaxagoras also seems to have supposed the happy man
not to be rich nor a despot, when he said that he would not be surprised
if the happy man were to seem to most people a strange person; for they
judge by externals, since these are all they perceive. The opinions of
the wise seem, then, to harmonize with our arguments. But while even such
things carry some conviction, the truth in practical matters is discerned
from the facts of life; for these are the decisive factor. We must therefore
survey what we have already said, bringing it to the test of the facts
of life, and if it harmonizes with the facts we must accept it, but if
it clashes with them we must suppose it to be mere theory. Now he who exercises
his reason and cultivates it seems to be both in the best state of mind
and most dear to the gods. For if the gods have any care for human affairs,
as they are thought to have, it would be reasonable both that they should
delight in that which was best and most akin to them (i.e. reason) and
that they should reward those who love and honour this most, as caring
for the things that are dear to them and acting both rightly and nobly.
And that all these attributes belong most of all to the philosopher is
manifest. He, therefore, is the dearest to the gods. And he who is that
will presumably be also the happiest; so that in this way too the philosopher
will more than any other be happy.
9
If these matters and the virtues, and also friendship and pleasure,
have been dealt with sufficiently in outline, are we to suppose that our
programme has reached its end? Surely, as the saying goes, where there
are things to be done the end is not to survey and recognize the various
things, but rather to do them; with regard to virtue, then, it is not enough
to know, but we must try to have and use it, or try any other way there
may be of becoming good. Now if arguments were in themselves enough to
make men good, they would justly, as Theognis says, have won very great
rewards, and such rewards should have been provided; but as things are,
while they seem to have power to encourage and stimulate the generous-minded
among our youth, and to make a character which is gently born, and a true
lover of what is noble, ready to be possessed by virtue, they are not able
to encourage the many to nobility and goodness. For these do not by nature
obey the sense of shame, but only fear, and do not abstain from bad acts
because of their baseness but through fear of punishment; living by passion
they pursue their own pleasures and the means to them, and and the opposite
pains, and have not even a conception of what is noble and truly pleasant,
since they have never tasted it. What argument would remould such people?
It is hard, if not impossible, to remove by argument the traits that have
long since been incorporated in the character; and perhaps we must be content
if, when all the influences by which we are thought to become good are
present, we get some tincture of virtue.
Now some think that we are made good by nature, others by habituation,
others by teaching. Nature's part evidently does not depend on us, but
as a result of some divine causes is present in those who are truly fortunate;
while argument and teaching, we may suspect, are not powerful with all
men, but the soul of the student must first have been cultivated by means
of habits for noble joy and noble hatred, like earth which is to nourish
the seed. For he who lives as passion directs will not hear argument that
dissuades him, nor understand it if he does; and how can we persuade one
in such a state to change his ways? And in general passion seems to yield
not to argument but to force. The character, then, must somehow be there
already with a kinship to virtue, loving what is noble and hating what
is base.
But it is difficult to get from youth up a right training for virtue
if one has not been brought up under right laws; for to live temperately
and hardily is not pleasant to most people, especially when they are young.
For this reason their nurture and occupations should be fixed by law; for
they will not be painful when they have become customary. But it is surely
not enough that when they are young they should get the right nurture and
attention; since they must, even when they are grown up, practise and be
habituated to them, we shall need laws for this as well, and generally
speaking to cover the whole of life; for most people obey necessity rather
than argument, and punishments rather than the sense of what is
noble.
This is why some think that legislators ought to stimulate men
to virtue and urge them forward by the motive of the noble, on the assumption
that those who have been well advanced by the formation of habits will
attend to such influences; and that punishments and penalties should be
imposed on those who disobey and are of inferior nature, while the incurably
bad should be completely banished. A good man (they think), since he lives
with his mind fixed on what is noble, will submit to argument, while a
bad man, whose desire is for pleasure, is corrected by pain like a beast
of burden. This is, too, why they say the pains inflicted should be those
that are most opposed to the pleasures such men love.
However that may be, if (as we have said) the man who is to be
good must be well trained and habituated, and go on to spend his time in
worthy occupations and neither willingly nor unwillingly do bad actions,
and if this can be brought about if men live in accordance with a sort
of reason and right order, provided this has force,-if this be so, the
paternal command indeed has not the required force or compulsive power
(nor in general has the command of one man, unless he be a king or something
similar), but the law has compulsive power, while it is at the same time
a rule proceeding from a sort of practical wisdom and reason. And while
people hate men who oppose their impulses, even if they oppose them rightly,
the law in its ordaining of what is good is not burdensome.
In the Spartan state alone, or almost alone, the legislator seems
to have paid attention to questions of nurture and occupations; in most
states such matters have been neglected, and each man lives as he pleases,
Cyclops-fashion, 'to his own wife and children dealing law'. Now it is
best that there should be a public and proper care for such matters; but
if they are neglected by the community it would seem right for each man
to help his children and friends towards virtue, and that they should have
the power, or at least the will, to do this.
It would seem from what has been said that he can do this better
if he makes himself capable of legislating. For public control is plainly
effected by laws, and good control by good laws; whether written or unwritten
would seem to make no difference, nor whether they are laws providing for
the education of individuals or of groups-any more than it does in the
case of music or gymnastics and other such pursuits. For as in cities laws
and prevailing types of character have force, so in households do the injunctions
and the habits of the father, and these have even more because of the tie
of blood and the benefits he confers; for the children start with a natural
affection and disposition to obey. Further, private education has an advantage
over public, as private medical treatment has; for while in general rest
and abstinence from food are good for a man in a fever, for a particular
man they may not be; and a boxer presumably does not prescribe the same
style of fighting to all his pupils. It would seem, then, that the detail
is worked out with more precision if the control is private; for each person
is more likely to get what suits his case.
But the details can be best looked after, one by one, by a doctor
or gymnastic instructor or any one else who has the general knowledge of
what is good for every one or for people of a certain kind (for the sciences
both are said to be, and are, concerned with what is universal); not but
what some particular detail may perhaps be well looked after by an unscientific
person, if he has studied accurately in the light of experience what happens
in each case, just as some people seem to be their own best doctors, though
they could give no help to any one else. None the less, it will perhaps
be agreed that if a man does wish to become master of an art or science
he must go to the universal, and come to know it as well as possible; for,
as we have said, it is with this that the sciences are
concerned.
And surely he who wants to make men, whether many or few, better
by his care must try to become capable of legislating, if it is through
laws that we can become good. For to get any one whatever-any one who is
put before us-into the right condition is not for the first chance comer;
if any one can do it, it is the man who knows, just as in medicine and
all other matters which give scope for care and prudence.
Must we not, then, next examine whence or how one can learn how
to legislate? Is it, as in all other cases, from statesmen? Certainly it
was thought to be a part of statesmanship. Or is a difference apparent
between statesmanship and the other sciences and arts? In the others the
same people are found offering to teach the arts and practising them, e.g.
doctors or painters; but while the sophists profess to teach politics,
it is practised not by any of them but by the politicians, who would seem
to do so by dint of a certain skill and experience rather than of thought;
for they are not found either writing or speaking about such matters (though
it were a nobler occupation perhaps than composing speeches for the law-courts
and the assembly), nor again are they found to have made statesmen of their
own sons or any other of their friends. But it was to be expected that
they should if they could; for there is nothing better than such a skill
that they could have left to their cities, or could prefer to have for
themselves, or, therefore, for those dearest to them. Still, experience
seems to contribute not a little; else they could not have become politicians
by familiarity with politics; and so it seems that those who aim at knowing
about the art of politics need experience as well.
But those of the sophists who profess the art seem to be very far
from teaching it. For, to put the matter generally, they do not even know
what kind of thing it is nor what kinds of things it is about; otherwise
they would not have classed it as identical with rhetoric or even inferior
to it, nor have thought it easy to legislate by collecting the laws that
are thought well of; they say it is possible to select the best laws, as
though even the selection did not demand intelligence and as though right
judgement were not the greatest thing, as in matters of music. For while
people experienced in any department judge rightly the works produced in
it, and understand by what means or how they are achieved, and what harmonizes
with what, the inexperienced must be content if they do not fail to see
whether the work has been well or ill made-as in the case of painting.
Now laws are as it were the' works' of the political art; how then can
one learn from them to be a legislator, or judge which are best? Even medical
men do not seem to be made by a study of text-books. Yet people try, at
any rate, to state not only the treatments, but also how particular classes
of people can be cured and should be treated-distinguishing the various
habits of body; but while this seems useful to experienced people, to the
inexperienced it is valueless. Surely, then, while collections of laws,
and of constitutions also, may be serviceable to those who can study them
and judge what is good or bad and what enactments suit what circumstances,
those who go through such collections without a practised faculty will
not have right judgement (unless it be as a spontaneous gift of nature),
though they may perhaps become more intelligent in such
matters.
Now our predecessors have left the subject of legislation to us
unexamined; it is perhaps best, therefore, that we should ourselves study
it, and in general study the question of the constitution, in order to
complete to the best of our ability our philosophy of human nature. First,
then, if anything has been said well in detail by earlier thinkers, let
us try to review it; then in the light of the constitutions we have collected
let us study what sorts of influence preserve and destroy states, and what
sorts preserve or destroy the particular kinds of constitution, and to
what causes it is due that some are well and others ill administered. When
these have been studied we shall perhaps be more likely to see with a comprehensive
view, which constitution is best, and how each must be ordered, and what
laws and customs it must use, if it is to be at its best. Let us make a
beginning of our discussion.
THE END