Nicomachean Ethics
By Aristotle
Commentary: Quite a few comments have been posted about
Nicomachean Ethics.
Download: A
text-only version is available for download.
Nicomachean Ethics
By Aristotle
Written 350 B.C.E
Translated by W. D. Ross
1
Since virtue is concerned with passions and actions, and on voluntary
passions and actions praise and blame are bestowed, on those that are involuntary
pardon, and sometimes also pity, to distinguish the voluntary and the involuntary
is presumably necessary for those who are studying the nature of virtue,
and useful also for legislators with a view to the assigning both of honours
and of punishments. Those things, then, are thought-involuntary, which
take place under compulsion or owing to ignorance; and that is compulsory
of which the moving principle is outside, being a principle in which nothing
is contributed by the person who is acting or is feeling the passion, e.g.
if he were to be carried somewhere by a wind, or by men who had him in
their power.
But with regard to the things that are done from fear of greater
evils or for some noble object (e.g. if a tyrant were to order one to do
something base, having one's parents and children in his power, and if
one did the action they were to be saved, but otherwise would be put to
death), it may be debated whether such actions are involuntary or voluntary.
Something of the sort happens also with regard to the throwing of goods
overboard in a storm; for in the abstract no one throws goods away voluntarily,
but on condition of its securing the safety of himself and his crew any
sensible man does so. Such actions, then, are mixed, but are more like
voluntary actions; for they are worthy of choice at the time when they
are done, and the end of an action is relative to the occasion. Both the
terms, then, 'voluntary' and 'involuntary', must be used with reference
to the moment of action. Now the man acts voluntarily; for the principle
that moves the instrumental parts of the body in such actions is in him,
and the things of which the moving principle is in a man himself are in
his power to do or not to do. Such actions, therefore, are voluntary, but
in the abstract perhaps involuntary; for no one would choose any such act
in itself.
For such actions men are sometimes even praised, when they endure
something base or painful in return for great and noble objects gained;
in the opposite case they are blamed, since to endure the greatest indignities
for no noble end or for a trifling end is the mark of an inferior person.
On some actions praise indeed is not bestowed, but pardon is, when one
does what he ought not under pressure which overstrains human nature and
which no one could withstand. But some acts, perhaps, we cannot be forced
to do, but ought rather to face death after the most fearful sufferings;
for the things that 'forced' Euripides Alcmaeon to slay his mother seem
absurd. It is difficult sometimes to determine what should be chosen at
what cost, and what should be endured in return for what gain, and yet
more difficult to abide by our decisions; for as a rule what is expected
is painful, and what we are forced to do is base, whence praise and blame
are bestowed on those who have been compelled or have
not.
What sort of acts, then, should be called compulsory? We answer
that without qualification actions are so when the cause is in the external
circumstances and the agent contributes nothing. But the things that in
themselves are involuntary, but now and in return for these gains are worthy
of choice, and whose moving principle is in the agent, are in themselves
involuntary, but now and in return for these gains voluntary. They are
more like voluntary acts; for actions are in the class of particulars,
and the particular acts here are voluntary. What sort of things are to
be chosen, and in return for what, it is not easy to state; for there are
many differences in the particular cases.
But if some one were to say that pleasant and noble objects have
a compelling power, forcing us from without, all acts would be for him
compulsory; for it is for these objects that all men do everything they
do. And those who act under compulsion and unwillingly act with pain, but
those who do acts for their pleasantness and nobility do them with pleasure;
it is absurd to make external circumstances responsible, and not oneself,
as being easily caught by such attractions, and to make oneself responsible
for noble acts but the pleasant objects responsible for base acts. The
compulsory, then, seems to be that whose moving principle is outside, the
person compelled contributing nothing.
Everything that is done by reason of ignorance is not voluntary;
it is only what produces pain and repentance that is involuntary. For the
man who has done something owing to ignorance, and feels not the least
vexation at his action, has not acted voluntarily, since he did not know
what he was doing, nor yet involuntarily, since he is not pained. Of people,
then, who act by reason of ignorance he who repents is thought an involuntary
agent, and the man who does not repent may, since he is different, be called
a not voluntary agent; for, since he differs from the other, it is better
that he should have a name of his own.
Acting by reason of ignorance seems also to be different from acting
in ignorance; for the man who is drunk or in a rage is thought to act as
a result not of ignorance but of one of the causes mentioned, yet not knowingly
but in ignorance.
Now every wicked man is ignorant of what he ought to do and what
he ought to abstain from, and it is by reason of error of this kind that
men become unjust and in general bad; but the term 'involuntary' tends
to be used not if a man is ignorant of what is to his advantage- for it
is not mistaken purpose that causes involuntary action (it leads rather
to wickedness), nor ignorance of the universal (for that men are blamed),
but ignorance of particulars, i.e. of the circumstances of the action and
the objects with which it is concerned. For it is on these that both pity
and pardon depend, since the person who is ignorant of any of these acts
involuntarily.
Perhaps it is just as well, therefore, to determine their nature
and number. A man may be ignorant, then, of who he is, what he is doing,
what or whom he is acting on, and sometimes also what (e.g. what instrument)
he is doing it with, and to what end (e.g. he may think his act will conduce
to some one's safety), and how he is doing it (e.g. whether gently or violently).
Now of all of these no one could be ignorant unless he were mad, and evidently
also he could not be ignorant of the agent; for how could he not know himself?
But of what he is doing a man might be ignorant, as for instance people
say 'it slipped out of their mouths as they were speaking', or 'they did
not know it was a secret', as Aeschylus said of the mysteries, or a man
might say he 'let it go off when he merely wanted to show its working',
as the man did with the catapult. Again, one might think one's son was
an enemy, as Merope did, or that a pointed spear had a button on it, or
that a stone was pumicestone; or one might give a man a draught to save
him, and really kill him; or one might want to touch a man, as people do
in sparring, and really wound him. The ignorance may relate, then, to any
of these things, i.e. of the circumstances of the action, and the man who
was ignorant of any of these is thought to have acted involuntarily, and
especially if he was ignorant on the most important points; and these are
thought to be the circumstances of the action and its end. Further, the
doing of an act that is called involuntary in virtue of ignorance of this
sort must be painful and involve repentance.
Since that which is done under compulsion or by reason of ignorance
is involuntary, the voluntary would seem to be that of which the moving
principle is in the agent himself, he being aware of the particular circumstances
of the action. Presumably acts done by reason of anger or appetite are
not rightly called involuntary. For in the first place, on that showing
none of the other animals will act voluntarily, nor will children; and
secondly, is it meant that we do not do voluntarily any of the acts that
are due to appetite or anger, or that we do the noble acts voluntarily
and the base acts involuntarily? Is not this absurd, when one and the same
thing is the cause? But it would surely be odd to describe as involuntary
the things one ought to desire; and we ought both to be angry at certain
things and to have an appetite for certain things, e.g. for health and
for learning. Also what is involuntary is thought to be painful, but what
is in accordance with appetite is thought to be pleasant. Again, what is
the difference in respect of involuntariness between errors committed upon
calculation and those committed in anger? Both are to be avoided, but the
irrational passions are thought not less human than reason is, and therefore
also the actions which proceed from anger or appetite are the man's actions.
It would be odd, then, to treat them as involuntary.
2
Both the voluntary and the involuntary having been delimited, we
must next discuss choice; for it is thought to be most closely bound up
with virtue and to discriminate characters better than actions
do.
Choice, then, seems to be voluntary, but not the same thing as
the voluntary; the latter extends more widely. For both children and the
lower animals share in voluntary action, but not in choice, and acts done
on the spur of the moment we describe as voluntary, but not as
chosen.
Those who say it is appetite or anger or wish or a kind of opinion
do not seem to be right. For choice is not common to irrational creatures
as well, but appetite and anger are. Again, the incontinent man acts with
appetite, but not with choice; while the continent man on the contrary
acts with choice, but not with appetite. Again, appetite is contrary to
choice, but not appetite to appetite. Again, appetite relates to the pleasant
and the painful, choice neither to the painful nor to the
pleasant.
Still less is it anger; for acts due to anger are thought to be
less than any others objects of choice.
But neither is it wish, though it seems near to it; for choice
cannot relate to impossibles, and if any one said he chose them he would
be thought silly; but there may be a wish even for impossibles, e.g. for
immortality. And wish may relate to things that could in no way be brought
about by one's own efforts, e.g. that a particular actor or athlete should
win in a competition; but no one chooses such things, but only the things
that he thinks could be brought about by his own efforts. Again, wish relates
rather to the end, choice to the means; for instance, we wish to be healthy,
but we choose the acts which will make us healthy, and we wish to be happy
and say we do, but we cannot well say we choose to be so; for, in general,
choice seems to relate to the things that are in our own
power.
For this reason, too, it cannot be opinion; for opinion is thought
to relate to all kinds of things, no less to eternal things and impossible
things than to things in our own power; and it is distinguished by its
falsity or truth, not by its badness or goodness, while choice is distinguished
rather by these.
Now with opinion in general perhaps no one even says it is identical.
But it is not identical even with any kind of opinion; for by choosing
what is good or bad we are men of a certain character, which we are not
by holding certain opinions. And we choose to get or avoid something good
or bad, but we have opinions about what a thing is or whom it is good for
or how it is good for him; we can hardly be said to opine to get or avoid
anything. And choice is praised for being related to the right object rather
than for being rightly related to it, opinion for being truly related to
its object. And we choose what we best know to be good, but we opine what
we do not quite know; and it is not the same people that are thought to
make the best choices and to have the best opinions, but some are thought
to have fairly good opinions, but by reason of vice to choose what they
should not. If opinion precedes choice or accompanies it, that makes no
difference; for it is not this that we are considering, but whether it
is identical with some kind of opinion.
What, then, or what kind of thing is it, since it is none of the
things we have mentioned? It seems to be voluntary, but not all that is
voluntary to be an object of choice. Is it, then, what has been decided
on by previous deliberation? At any rate choice involves a rational principle
and thought. Even the name seems to suggest that it is what is chosen before
other things.
3
Do we deliberate about everything, and is everything a possible
subject of deliberation, or is deliberation impossible about some things?
We ought presumably to call not what a fool or a madman would deliberate
about, but what a sensible man would deliberate about, a subject of deliberation.
Now about eternal things no one deliberates, e.g. about the material universe
or the incommensurability of the diagonal and the side of a square. But
no more do we deliberate about the things that involve movement but always
happen in the same way, whether of necessity or by nature or from any other
cause, e.g. the solstices and the risings of the stars; nor about things
that happen now in one way, now in another, e.g. droughts and rains; nor
about chance events, like the finding of treasure. But we do not deliberate
even about all human affairs; for instance, no Spartan deliberates about
the best constitution for the Scythians. For none of these things can be
brought about by our own efforts.
We deliberate about things that are in our power and can be done;
and these are in fact what is left. For nature, necessity, and chance are
thought to be causes, and also reason and everything that depends on man.
Now every class of men deliberates about the things that can be done by
their own efforts. And in the case of exact and self-contained sciences
there is no deliberation, e.g. about the letters of the alphabet (for we
have no doubt how they should be written); but the things that are brought
about by our own efforts, but not always in the same way, are the things
about which we deliberate, e.g. questions of medical treatment or of money-making.
And we do so more in the case of the art of navigation than in that of
gymnastics, inasmuch as it has been less exactly worked out, and again
about other things in the same ratio, and more also in the case of the
arts than in that of the sciences; for we have more doubt about the former.
Deliberation is concerned with things that happen in a certain way for
the most part, but in which the event is obscure, and with things in which
it is indeterminate. We call in others to aid us in deliberation on important
questions, distrusting ourselves as not being equal to
deciding.
We deliberate not about ends but about means. For a doctor does
not deliberate whether he shall heal, nor an orator whether he shall persuade,
nor a statesman whether he shall produce law and order, nor does any one
else deliberate about his end. They assume the end and consider how and
by what means it is to be attained; and if it seems to be produced by several
means they consider by which it is most easily and best produced, while
if it is achieved by one only they consider how it will be achieved by
this and by what means this will be achieved, till they come to the first
cause, which in the order of discovery is last. For the person who deliberates
seems to investigate and analyse in the way described as though he were
analysing a geometrical construction (not all investigation appears to
be deliberation- for instance mathematical investigations- but all deliberation
is investigation), and what is last in the order of analysis seems to be
first in the order of becoming. And if we come on an impossibility, we
give up the search, e.g. if we need money and this cannot be got; but if
a thing appears possible we try to do it. By 'possible' things I mean things
that might be brought about by our own efforts; and these in a sense include
things that can be brought about by the efforts of our friends, since the
moving principle is in ourselves. The subject of investigation is sometimes
the instruments, sometimes the use of them; and similarly in the other
cases- sometimes the means, sometimes the mode of using it or the means
of bringing it about. It seems, then, as has been said, that man is a moving
principle of actions; now deliberation is about the things to be done by
the agent himself, and actions are for the sake of things other than themselves.
For the end cannot be a subject of deliberation, but only the means; nor
indeed can the particular facts be a subject of it, as whether this is
bread or has been baked as it should; for these are matters of perception.
If we are to be always deliberating, we shall have to go on to
infinity.
The same thing is deliberated upon and is chosen, except that the
object of choice is already determinate, since it is that which has been
decided upon as a result of deliberation that is the object of choice.
For every one ceases to inquire how he is to act when he has brought the
moving principle back to himself and to the ruling part of himself; for
this is what chooses. This is plain also from the ancient constitutions,
which Homer represented; for the kings announced their choices to the people.
The object of choice being one of the things in our own power which is
desired after deliberation, choice will be deliberate desire of things
in our own power; for when we have decided as a result of deliberation,
we desire in accordance with our deliberation.
We may take it, then, that we have described choice in outline,
and stated the nature of its objects and the fact that it is concerned
with means.
4
That wish is for the end has already been stated; some think it
is for the good, others for the apparent good. Now those who say that the
good is the object of wish must admit in consequence that that which the
man who does not choose aright wishes for is not an object of wish (for
if it is to be so, it must also be good; but it was, if it so happened,
bad); while those who say the apparent good is the object of wish must
admit that there is no natural object of wish, but only what seems good
to each man. Now different things appear good to different people, and,
if it so happens, even contrary things.
If these consequences are unpleasing, are we to say that absolutely
and in truth the good is the object of wish, but for each person the apparent
good; that that which is in truth an object of wish is an object of wish
to the good man, while any chance thing may be so the bad man, as in the
case of bodies also the things that are in truth wholesome are wholesome
for bodies which are in good condition, while for those that are diseased
other things are wholesome- or bitter or sweet or hot or heavy, and so
on; since the good man judges each class of things rightly, and in each
the truth appears to him? For each state of character has its own ideas
of the noble and the pleasant, and perhaps the good man differs from others
most by seeing the truth in each class of things, being as it were the
norm and measure of them. In most things the error seems to be due to pleasure;
for it appears a good when it is not. We therefore choose the pleasant
as a good, and avoid pain as an evil.
5
The end, then, being what we wish for, the means what we deliberate
about and choose, actions concerning means must be according to choice
and voluntary. Now the exercise of the virtues is concerned with means.
Therefore virtue also is in our own power, and so too vice. For where it
is in our power to act it is also in our power not to act, and vice versa;
so that, if to act, where this is noble, is in our power, not to act, which
will be base, will also be in our power, and if not to act, where this
is noble, is in our power, to act, which will be base, will also be in
our power. Now if it is in our power to do noble or base acts, and likewise
in our power not to do them, and this was what being good or bad meant,
then it is in our power to be virtuous or vicious.
The saying that 'no one is voluntarily wicked nor involuntarily
happy' seems to be partly false and partly true; for no one is involuntarily
happy, but wickedness is voluntary. Or else we shall have to dispute what
has just been said, at any rate, and deny that man is a moving principle
or begetter of his actions as of children. But if these facts are evident
and we cannot refer actions to moving principles other than those in ourselves,
the acts whose moving principles are in us must themselves also be in our
power and voluntary.
Witness seems to be borne to this both by individuals in their
private capacity and by legislators themselves; for these punish and take
vengeance on those who do wicked acts (unless they have acted under compulsion
or as a result of ignorance for which they are not themselves responsible),
while they honour those who do noble acts, as though they meant to encourage
the latter and deter the former. But no one is encouraged to do the things
that are neither in our power nor voluntary; it is assumed that there is
no gain in being persuaded not to be hot or in pain or hungry or the like,
since we shall experience these feelings none the less. Indeed, we punish
a man for his very ignorance, if he is thought responsible for the ignorance,
as when penalties are doubled in the case of drunkenness; for the moving
principle is in the man himself, since he had the power of not getting
drunk and his getting drunk was the cause of his ignorance. And we punish
those who are ignorant of anything in the laws that they ought to know
and that is not difficult, and so too in the case of anything else that
they are thought to be ignorant of through carelessness; we assume that
it is in their power not to be ignorant, since they have the power of taking
care.
But perhaps a man is the kind of man not to take care. Still they
are themselves by their slack lives responsible for becoming men of that
kind, and men make themselves responsible for being unjust or self-indulgent,
in the one case by cheating and in the other by spending their time in
drinking bouts and the like; for it is activities exercised on particular
objects that make the corresponding character. This is plain from the case
of people training for any contest or action; they practise the activity
the whole time. Now not to know that it is from the exercise of activities
on particular objects that states of character are produced is the mark
of a thoroughly senseless person. Again, it is irrational to suppose that
a man who acts unjustly does not wish to be unjust or a man who acts self-indulgently
to be self-indulgent. But if without being ignorant a man does the things
which will make him unjust, he will be unjust voluntarily. Yet it does
not follow that if he wishes he will cease to be unjust and will be just.
For neither does the man who is ill become well on those terms. We may
suppose a case in which he is ill voluntarily, through living incontinently
and disobeying his doctors. In that case it was then open to him not to
be ill, but not now, when he has thrown away his chance, just as when you
have let a stone go it is too late to recover it; but yet it was in your
power to throw it, since the moving principle was in you. So, too, to the
unjust and to the self-indulgent man it was open at the beginning not to
become men of this kind, and so they are unjust and selfindulgent voluntarily;
but now that they have become so it is not possible for them not to be
so.
But not only are the vices of the soul voluntary, but those of
the body also for some men, whom we accordingly blame; while no one blames
those who are ugly by nature, we blame those who are so owing to want of
exercise and care. So it is, too, with respect to weakness and infirmity;
no one would reproach a man blind from birth or by disease or from a blow,
but rather pity him, while every one would blame a man who was blind from
drunkenness or some other form of self-indulgence. Of vices of the body,
then, those in our own power are blamed, those not in our power are not.
And if this be so, in the other cases also the vices that are blamed must
be in our own power.
Now some one may say that all men desire the apparent good, but
have no control over the appearance, but the end appears to each man in
a form answering to his character. We reply that if each man is somehow
responsible for his state of mind, he will also be himself somehow responsible
for the appearance; but if not, no one is responsible for his own evildoing,
but every one does evil acts through ignorance of the end, thinking that
by these he will get what is best, and the aiming at the end is not self-chosen
but one must be born with an eye, as it were, by which to judge rightly
and choose what is truly good, and he is well endowed by nature who is
well endowed with this. For it is what is greatest and most noble, and
what we cannot get or learn from another, but must have just such as it
was when given us at birth, and to be well and nobly endowed with this
will be perfect and true excellence of natural endowment. If this is true,
then, how will virtue be more voluntary than vice? To both men alike, the
good and the bad, the end appears and is fixed by nature or however it
may be, and it is by referring everything else to this that men do whatever
they do.
Whether, then, it is not by nature that the end appears to each
man such as it does appear, but something also depends on him, or the end
is natural but because the good man adopts the means voluntarily virtue
is voluntary, vice also will be none the less voluntary; for in the case
of the bad man there is equally present that which depends on himself in
his actions even if not in his end. If, then, as is asserted, the virtues
are voluntary (for we are ourselves somehow partly responsible for our
states of character, and it is by being persons of a certain kind that
we assume the end to be so and so), the vices also will be voluntary; for
the same is true of them.
With regard to the virtues in general we have stated their genus
in outline, viz. that they are means and that they are states of character,
and that they tend, and by their own nature, to the doing of the acts by
which they are produced, and that they are in our power and voluntary,
and act as the right rule prescribes. But actions and states of character
are not voluntary in the same way; for we are masters of our actions from
the beginning right to the end, if we know the particular facts, but though
we control the beginning of our states of character the gradual progress
is not obvious any more than it is in illnesses; because it was in our
power, however, to act in this way or not in this way, therefore the states
are voluntary.
Let us take up the several virtues, however, and say which they
are and what sort of things they are concerned with and how they are concerned
with them; at the same time it will become plain how many they are. And
first let us speak of courage.
6
That it is a mean with regard to feelings of fear and confidence
has already been made evident; and plainly the things we fear are terrible
things, and these are, to speak without qualification, evils; for which
reason people even define fear as expectation of evil. Now we fear all
evils, e.g. disgrace, poverty, disease, friendlessness, death, but the
brave man is not thought to be concerned with all; for to fear some things
is even right and noble, and it is base not to fear them- e.g. disgrace;
he who fears this is good and modest, and he who does not is shameless.
He is, however, by some people called brave, by a transference of the word
to a new meaning; for he has in him something which is like the brave man,
since the brave man also is a fearless person. Poverty and disease we perhaps
ought not to fear, nor in general the things that do not proceed from vice
and are not due to a man himself. But not even the man who is fearless
of these is brave. Yet we apply the word to him also in virtue of a similarity;
for some who in the dangers of war are cowards are liberal and are confident
in face of the loss of money. Nor is a man a coward if he fears insult
to his wife and children or envy or anything of the kind; nor brave if
he is confident when he is about to be flogged. With what sort of terrible
things, then, is the brave man concerned? Surely with the greatest; for
no one is more likely than he to stand his ground against what is awe-inspiring.
Now death is the most terrible of all things; for it is the end, and nothing
is thought to be any longer either good or bad for the dead. But the brave
man would not seem to be concerned even with death in all circumstances,
e.g. at sea or in disease. In what circumstances, then? Surely in the noblest.
Now such deaths are those in battle; for these take place in the greatest
and noblest danger. And these are correspondingly honoured in city-states
and at the courts of monarchs. Properly, then, he will be called brave
who is fearless in face of a noble death, and of all emergencies that involve
death; and the emergencies of war are in the highest degree of this kind.
Yet at sea also, and in disease, the brave man is fearless, but not in
the same way as the seaman; for he has given up hope of safety, and is
disliking the thought of death in this shape, while they are hopeful because
of their experience. At the same time, we show courage in situations where
there is the opportunity of showing prowess or where death is noble; but
in these forms of death neither of these conditions is
fulfilled.
7
What is terrible is not the same for all men; but we say there
are things terrible even beyond human strength. These, then, are terrible
to every one- at least to every sensible man; but the terrible things that
are not beyond human strength differ in magnitude and degree, and so too
do the things that inspire confidence. Now the brave man is as dauntless
as man may be. Therefore, while he will fear even the things that are not
beyond human strength, he will face them as he ought and as the rule directs,
for honour's sake; for this is the end of virtue. But it is possible to
fear these more, or less, and again to fear things that are not terrible
as if they were. Of the faults that are committed one consists in fearing
what one should not, another in fearing as we should not, another in fearing
when we should not, and so on; and so too with respect to the things that
inspire confidence. The man, then, who faces and who fears the right things
and from the right motive, in the right way and from the right time, and
who feels confidence under the corresponding conditions, is brave; for
the brave man feels and acts according to the merits of the case and in
whatever way the rule directs. Now the end of every activity is conformity
to the corresponding state of character. This is true, therefore, of the
brave man as well as of others. But courage is noble. Therefore the end
also is noble; for each thing is defined by its end. Therefore it is for
a noble end that the brave man endures and acts as courage
directs.
Of those who go to excess he who exceeds in fearlessness has no
name (we have said previously that many states of character have no names),
but he would be a sort of madman or insensible person if he feared nothing,
neither earthquakes nor the waves, as they say the Celts do not; while
the man who exceeds in confidence about what really is terrible is rash.
The rash man, however, is also thought to be boastful and only a pretender
to courage; at all events, as the brave man is with regard to what is terrible,
so the rash man wishes to appear; and so he imitates him in situations
where he can. Hence also most of them are a mixture of rashness and cowardice;
for, while in these situations they display confidence, they do not hold
their ground against what is really terrible. The man who exceeds in fear
is a coward; for he fears both what he ought not and as he ought not, and
all the similar characterizations attach to him. He is lacking also in
confidence; but he is more conspicuous for his excess of fear in painful
situations. The coward, then, is a despairing sort of person; for he fears
everything. The brave man, on the other hand, has the opposite disposition;
for confidence is the mark of a hopeful disposition. The coward, the rash
man, and the brave man, then, are concerned with the same objects but are
differently disposed towards them; for the first two exceed and fall short,
while the third holds the middle, which is the right, position; and rash
men are precipitate, and wish for dangers beforehand but draw back when
they are in them, while brave men are keen in the moment of action, but
quiet beforehand.
As we have said, then, courage is a mean with respect to things
that inspire confidence or fear, in the circumstances that have been stated;
and it chooses or endures things because it is noble to do so, or because
it is base not to do so. But to die to escape from poverty or love or anything
painful is not the mark of a brave man, but rather of a coward; for it
is softness to fly from what is troublesome, and such a man endures death
not because it is noble but to fly from evil.
8
Courage, then, is something of this sort, but the name is also
applied to five other kinds.
First comes the courage of the citizen-soldier; for this is most
like true courage. Citizen-soldiers seem to face dangers because of the
penalties imposed by the laws and the reproaches they would otherwise incur,
and because of the honours they win by such action; and therefore those
peoples seem to be bravest among whom cowards are held in dishonour and
brave men in honour. This is the kind of courage that Homer depicts, e.g.
in Diomede and in Hector:
First will Polydamas be to heap reproach on me then;
and
For Hector one day 'mid the Trojans shall utter his
vaulting
harangue:
Afraid was Tydeides, and fled from my face.
This kind of courage is most like to that which we described earlier,
because it is due to virtue; for it is due to shame and to desire of a
noble object (i.e. honour) and avoidance of disgrace, which is ignoble.
One might rank in the same class even those who are compelled by their
rulers; but they are inferior, inasmuch as they do what they do not from
shame but from fear, and to avoid not what is disgraceful but what is painful;
for their masters compel them, as Hector does:
But if I shall spy any dastard that cowers far from the
fight,
Vainly will such an one hope to escape from the
dogs.
And those who give them their posts, and beat them if they retreat,
do the same, and so do those who draw them up with trenches or something
of the sort behind them; all of these apply compulsion. But one ought to
be brave not under compulsion but because it is noble to be
so.
(2) Experience with regard to particular facts is also thought
to be courage; this is indeed the reason why Socrates thought courage was
knowledge. Other people exhibit this quality in other dangers, and professional
soldiers exhibit it in the dangers of war; for there seem to be many empty
alarms in war, of which these have had the most comprehensive experience;
therefore they seem brave, because the others do not know the nature of
the facts. Again, their experience makes them most capable in attack and
in defence, since they can use their arms and have the kind that are likely
to be best both for attack and for defence; therefore they fight like armed
men against unarmed or like trained athletes against amateurs; for in such
contests too it is not the bravest men that fight best, but those who are
strongest and have their bodies in the best condition. Professional soldiers
turn cowards, however, when the danger puts too great a strain on them
and they are inferior in numbers and equipment; for they are the first
to fly, while citizen-forces die at their posts, as in fact happened at
the temple of Hermes. For to the latter flight is disgraceful and death
is preferable to safety on those terms; while the former from the very
beginning faced the danger on the assumption that they were stronger, and
when they know the facts they fly, fearing death more than disgrace; but
the brave man is not that sort of person.
(3) Passion also is sometimes reckoned as courage; those who act
from passion, like wild beasts rushing at those who have wounded them,
are thought to be brave, because brave men also are passionate; for passion
above all things is eager to rush on danger, and hence Homer's 'put strength
into his passion' and 'aroused their spirit and passion and 'hard he breathed
panting' and 'his blood boiled'. For all such expressions seem to indicate
the stirring and onset of passion. Now brave men act for honour's sake,
but passion aids them; while wild beasts act under the influence of pain;
for they attack because they have been wounded or because they are afraid,
since if they are in a forest they do not come near one. Thus they are
not brave because, driven by pain and passion, they rush on danger without
foreseeing any of the perils, since at that rate even asses would be brave
when they are hungry; for blows will not drive them from their food; and
lust also makes adulterers do many daring things. (Those creatures are
not brave, then, which are driven on to danger by pain or passion.) The
'courage' that is due to passion seems to be the most natural, and to be
courage if choice and motive be added.
Men, then, as well as beasts, suffer pain when they are angry,
and are pleased when they exact their revenge; those who fight for these
reasons, however, are pugnacious but not brave; for they do not act for
honour's sake nor as the rule directs, but from strength of feeling; they
have, however, something akin to courage.
(4) Nor are sanguine people brave; for they are confident in danger
only because they have conquered often and against many foes. Yet they
closely resemble brave men, because both are confident; but brave men are
confident for the reasons stated earlier, while these are so because they
think they are the strongest and can suffer nothing. (Drunken men also
behave in this way; they become sanguine). When their adventures do not
succeed, however, they run away; but it was the mark of a brave man to
face things that are, and seem, terrible for a man, because it is noble
to do so and disgraceful not to do so. Hence also it is thought the mark
of a braver man to be fearless and undisturbed in sudden alarms than to
be so in those that are foreseen; for it must have proceeded more from
a state of character, because less from preparation; acts that are foreseen
may be chosen by calculation and rule, but sudden actions must be in accordance
with one's state of character.
(5) People who are ignorant of the danger also appear brave, and
they are not far removed from those of a sanguine temper, but are inferior
inasmuch as they have no self-reliance while these have. Hence also the
sanguine hold their ground for a time; but those who have been deceived
about the facts fly if they know or suspect that these are different from
what they supposed, as happened to the Argives when they fell in with the
Spartans and took them for Sicyonians.
We have, then, described the character both of brave men and of
those who are thought to be brave.
9
Though courage is concerned with feelings of confidence and of
fear, it is not concerned with both alike, but more with the things that
inspire fear; for he who is undisturbed in face of these and bears himself
as he should towards these is more truly brave than the man who does so
towards the things that inspire confidence. It is for facing what is painful,
then, as has been said, that men are called brave. Hence also courage involves
pain, and is justly praised; for it is harder to face what is painful than
to abstain from what is pleasant.
Yet the end which courage sets before it would seem to be pleasant,
but to be concealed by the attending circumstances, as happens also in
athletic contests; for the end at which boxers aim is pleasant- the crown
and the honours- but the blows they take are distressing to flesh and blood,
and painful, and so is their whole exertion; and because the blows and
the exertions are many the end, which is but small, appears to have nothing
pleasant in it. And so, if the case of courage is similar, death and wounds
will be painful to the brave man and against his will, but he will face
them because it is noble to do so or because it is base not to do so. And
the more he is possessed of virtue in its entirety and the happier he is,
the more he will be pained at the thought of death; for life is best worth
living for such a man, and he is knowingly losing the greatest goods, and
this is painful. But he is none the less brave, and perhaps all the more
so, because he chooses noble deeds of war at that cost. It is not the case,
then, with all the virtues that the exercise of them is pleasant, except
in so far as it reaches its end. But it is quite possible that the best
soldiers may be not men of this sort but those who are less brave but have
no other good; for these are ready to face danger, and they sell their
life for trifling gains.
So much, then, for courage; it is not difficult to grasp its nature
in outline, at any rate, from what has been said.
10
After courage let us speak of temperance; for these seem to be
the virtues of the irrational parts. We have said that temperance is a
mean with regard to pleasures (for it is less, and not in the same way,
concerned with pains); self-indulgence also is manifested in the same sphere.
Now, therefore, let us determine with what sort of pleasures they are concerned.
We may assume the distinction between bodily pleasures and those of the
soul, such as love of honour and love of learning; for the lover of each
of these delights in that of which he is a lover, the body being in no
way affected, but rather the mind; but men who are concerned with such
pleasures are called neither temperate nor self-indulgent. Nor, again,
are those who are concerned with the other pleasures that are not bodily;
for those who are fond of hearing and telling stories and who spend their
days on anything that turns up are called gossips, but not self-indulgent,
nor are those who are pained at the loss of money or of
friends.
Temperance must be concerned with bodily pleasures, but not all
even of these; for those who delight in objects of vision, such as colours
and shapes and painting, are called neither temperate nor self-indulgent;
yet it would seem possible to delight even in these either as one should
or to excess or to a deficient degree.
And so too is it with objects of hearing; no one calls those who
delight extravagantly in music or acting self-indulgent, nor those who
do so as they ought temperate.
Nor do we apply these names to those who delight in odour, unless
it be incidentally; we do not call those self-indulgent who delight in
the odour of apples or roses or incense, but rather those who delight in
the odour of unguents or of dainty dishes; for self-indulgent people delight
in these because these remind them of the objects of their appetite. And
one may see even other people, when they are hungry, delighting in the
smell of food; but to delight in this kind of thing is the mark of the
self-indulgent man; for these are objects of appetite to
him.
Nor is there in animals other than man any pleasure connected with
these senses, except incidentally. For dogs do not delight in the scent
of hares, but in the eating of them, but the scent told them the hares
were there; nor does the lion delight in the lowing of the ox, but in eating
it; but he perceived by the lowing that it was near, and therefore appears
to delight in the lowing; and similarly he does not delight because he
sees 'a stag or a wild goat', but because he is going to make a meal of
it. Temperance and self-indulgence, however, are concerned with the kind
of pleasures that the other animals share in, which therefore appear slavish
and brutish; these are touch and taste. But even of taste they appear to
make little or no use; for the business of taste is the discriminating
of flavours, which is done by winetasters and people who season dishes;
but they hardly take pleasure in making these discriminations, or at least
self-indulgent people do not, but in the actual enjoyment, which in all
cases comes through touch, both in the case of food and in that of drink
and in that of sexual intercourse. This is why a certain gourmand prayed
that his throat might become longer than a crane's, implying that it was
the contact that he took pleasure in. Thus the sense with which self-indulgence
is connected is the most widely shared of the senses; and self-indulgence
would seem to be justly a matter of reproach, because it attaches to us
not as men but as animals. To delight in such things, then, and to love
them above all others, is brutish. For even of the pleasures of touch the
most liberal have been eliminated, e.g. those produced in the gymnasium
by rubbing and by the consequent heat; for the contact characteristic of
the self-indulgent man does not affect the whole body but only certain
parts.
11
Of the appetites some seem to be common, others to be peculiar
to individuals and acquired; e.g. the appetite for food is natural, since
every one who is without it craves for food or drink, and sometimes for
both, and for love also (as Homer says) if he is young and lusty; but not
every one craves for this or that kind of nourishment or love, nor for
the same things. Hence such craving appears to be our very own. Yet it
has of course something natural about it; for different things are pleasant
to different kinds of people, and some things are more pleasant to every
one than chance objects. Now in the natural appetites few go wrong, and
only in one direction, that of excess; for to eat or drink whatever offers
itself till one is surfeited is to exceed the natural amount, since natural
appetite is the replenishment of one's deficiency. Hence these people are
called belly-gods, this implying that they fill their belly beyond what
is right. It is people of entirely slavish character that become like this.
But with regard to the pleasures peculiar to individuals many people go
wrong and in many ways. For while the people who are 'fond of so and so'
are so called because they delight either in the wrong things, or more
than most people do, or in the wrong way, the self-indulgent exceed in
all three ways; they both delight in some things that they ought not to
delight in (since they are hateful), and if one ought to delight in some
of the things they delight in, they do so more than one ought and than
most men do.
Plainly, then, excess with regard to pleasures is self-indulgence
and is culpable; with regard to pains one is not, as in the case of courage,
called temperate for facing them or self-indulgent for not doing so, but
the selfindulgent man is so called because he is pained more than he ought
at not getting pleasant things (even his pain being caused by pleasure),
and the temperate man is so called because he is not pained at the absence
of what is pleasant and at his abstinence from it.
The self-indulgent man, then, craves for all pleasant things or
those that are most pleasant, and is led by his appetite to choose these
at the cost of everything else; hence he is pained both when he fails to
get them and when he is merely craving for them (for appetite involves
pain); but it seems absurd to be pained for the sake of pleasure. People
who fall short with regard to pleasures and delight in them less than they
should are hardly found; for such insensibility is not human. Even the
other animals distinguish different kinds of food and enjoy some and not
others; and if there is any one who finds nothing pleasant and nothing
more attractive than anything else, he must be something quite different
from a man; this sort of person has not received a name because he hardly
occurs. The temperate man occupies a middle position with regard to these
objects. For he neither enjoys the things that the self-indulgent man enjoys
most-but rather dislikes them-nor in general the things that he should
not, nor anything of this sort to excess, nor does he feel pain or craving
when they are absent, or does so only to a moderate degree, and not more
than he should, nor when he should not, and so on; but the things that,
being pleasant, make for health or for good condition, he will desire moderately
and as he should, and also other pleasant things if they are not hindrances
to these ends, or contrary to what is noble, or beyond his means. For he
who neglects these conditions loves such pleasures more than they are worth,
but the temperate man is not that sort of person, but the sort of person
that the right rule prescribes.
12
Self-indulgence is more like a voluntary state than cowardice.
For the former is actuated by pleasure, the latter by pain, of which the
one is to be chosen and the other to be avoided; and pain upsets and destroys
the nature of the person who feels it, while pleasure does nothing of the
sort. Therefore self-indulgence is more voluntary. Hence also it is more
a matter of reproach; for it is easier to become accustomed to its objects,
since there are many things of this sort in life, and the process of habituation
to them is free from danger, while with terrible objects the reverse is
the case. But cowardice would seem to be voluntary in a different degree
from its particular manifestations; for it is itself painless, but in these
we are upset by pain, so that we even throw down our arms and disgrace
ourselves in other ways; hence our acts are even thought to be done under
compulsion. For the self-indulgent man, on the other hand, the particular
acts are voluntary (for he does them with craving and desire), but the
whole state is less so; for no one craves to be self-indulgent.
The name self-indulgence is applied also to childish faults; for
they bear a certain resemblance to what we have been considering. Which
is called after which, makes no difference to our present purpose; plainly,
however, the later is called after the earlier. The transference of the
name seems not a bad one; for that which desires what is base and which
develops quickly ought to be kept in a chastened condition, and these characteristics
belong above all to appetite and to the child, since children in fact live
at the beck and call of appetite, and it is in them that the desire for
what is pleasant is strongest. If, then, it is not going to be obedient
and subject to the ruling principle, it will go to great lengths; for in
an irrational being the desire for pleasure is insatiable even if it tries
every source of gratification, and the exercise of appetite increases its
innate force, and if appetites are strong and violent they even expel the
power of calculation. Hence they should be moderate and few, and should
in no way oppose the rational principle-and this is what we call an obedient
and chastened state-and as the child should live according to the direction
of his tutor, so the appetitive element should live according to rational
principle. Hence the appetitive element in a temperate man should harmonize
with the rational principle; for the noble is the mark at which both aim,
and the temperate man craves for the things be ought, as he ought, as when
he ought; and when he ought; and this is what rational principle
directs.
Here we conclude our account of temperance.